Lecture 30 Criticisms of Prospect Theory
Sairam
- Introduction
- PT around for over 3 decades
- non-conventional and radical nature \(\implies\) criticisms
- both theoretical and empirical
- Distinction between PT and CPT is important
- Theory is contradictory, unclear and contradictory
- Empirically, assumptions are violated and makes incorrect predictions
- Theoretical Criticisms
- Lack of normative status
- Internal Contradictions
- Birnbaum #economist
- Editing rules are 'imprecise, contradictory and conflict with the equations of PT'
- Can explain most results ex post1 by applying editing rules selectively (can only explain)
- \(\implies\) Cannot be used for predictions ex ante2 (cannot predict)
- Experiment
- Urn \(A:\) 1 red ($100), 1 blue ($100) and 98 white ($0)
- Urn \(B:\) 1 red ($100), 2 green ($45) and 97 white ($0)
- Choice 1
- \(A = (0.01,100;0.01,100;0.98,0)\)
- \(B = (0.01,100;0.02,45; 0.97,0)\)
- Choice 2 (after combination of choice 1)
- \(A' = (0.02,100;0.98,0)\)
- \(B = (0.01,100;0.02,45; 0.97,0)\)
- Choice 3 (after cancellation of choice 1)
- \(A'' = (0.01,100;0.99,0)\)
- \(B = (0.02,45; 0.97,0)\)
- \(\implies\) May lead to preference reversal. Application of editing rules lead to inconsistent preferences
- Incompleteness
- Determination of Reference points
- Weakness of PT: not determined endogenously
- determination is necessary:
- estimate incidence and effects of loss-aversion
- endowment effect
- Value of object given for free (gift) \(\ll\) earned (efforts) in some way
- K&T use existing situation as the reference point or an \(E[\text{Situation}]\)
- Precision in determination method would be useful e.g.
- to know if different types of investors have the same reference point?
- dynamic adjustment of reference points over time etc
-
Empirical Criticisms
- Violations of the Combination Principle
- Violation of Stochastic Dominance
-
Failure to explain Allais Paradox
- Birnbaum #economist
- Based on 200 participants' data:
Neither OPT nor CPT with or without editing principles of cancellation and combination can account for the Allais paradoxes
-
Loss aversion
- Cannot explain why DM find symmetrical bets like lotteries of the form \((0.5, x; 0.5, -x)\) unattractive.
- A #study by Adam & Kroll #psychologist
- 50 risk averse subjects
- choose between \((0.5, y+x; 0.5 y-x)\) vs \((y)\)
- PT predicted \((y)\) because of loss-aversion
- But 96% of the subjects played at least \(\dfrac{1}{25}\) lotteries (average 15.9 played)
- \(\implies\) Evidence for Theory of Attraction to Chance caused by emotional factors
- Violations of gain loss separability
- For mixed prospects, CPT evaluates gains and losses separately
- Assumes Gain-loss separability: Good part of B \(\succ\) Good part of A and Bad part of B \(\succ\) Bad part of A \(\implies\) \(B \succ A\)
- Wu and Markle 2008 #psychologist showed evidence for preference reversal: Mixed gamble \(A \succ B\) but individual loss and gains portion-wise \(B \succ A\)
- Nature of the utility function - Endowment Effects
- Levy & Levy (LL) #economist 2002
- Original K&T data didn't provide a reliable indicator to the shape of the utility functions
- Always asked subjects to choose between prospects both either positive and negative
- Reality: most prospects are mixed (e.g. stock market, either gain or loss)
- A #study included asking respondents for mixed prospects
- Objective:
- test S-shaped utility function = Markowitz model
- test reversed S-shaped function
- Sample - 260 subjects: business students, faculty from institutions (large number of professional practitioners)
- Experiment
- Consider investing $10,000 in stock
- Choose between
- \(F: (-3000, 0.5; 4500, 0.5)\)
- \(G: (-6000, 0.25; 3000, 0.75)\)
- both mixed, same expected values
- Sam gain and loss components: -1500 and 2250
- According to PT:
- risk-averse in gains, so prefer gain of 3000,0.75 \(\implies\) \(G \succ F\)
- risk-seeking in losses, so prefer loss of 6000,0.25 \(\implies\) \(G \succ F\)
- So, G is dominant
- However...
- LL: \(71\%\) preferred \(F\) which supported the Markowitz model
- \(\implies\) strong evidence against PT
- Objective:
- Discovered preference hypothesis and misconceptions
- Nature of Framing effects
- Inconsistency to explain framing effects
- Types of framing effects
- Standard risky choice (PT explains this best)
- Attribute framing
- Goal framing
- Doesn't explain the the other two
- Framing effects depends on
- task
- content
- context, inherent in the choice problem
- E.g. of Asian Disease
- Context: 600 citizens' life at threat
- Positive Frame: choice between
- saving 200 lives
- 2/3 chance of killing all
- Negative Frame
- 400 dying with certainty
- 1/3 of nobody dying
- Several studies argued that this approach confounded the framing and reflection effect
- Framing effect depends on negation 'not'
- Reflection effect depends on domain: gain or loss
- e.g. '200 people will be saved'
- positive frame
- positive domain (gain)
- '400 people will die'
- negative frame
- negative domain (loss)
- \(\implies\) In the K&T treatment, it is impossible to disentangle framing and reflection effects
- But it can be also argued
- '400 people will not be saved' has...
- negative frame
- positive domain
- '200 people will not be saved' has...
- positive frame
- negative domain
- '400 people will not be saved' has...
- \(\implies\) So we can restate A and C to test PT against other theories.
- Violations of the Combination Principle