Skip to content

Lecture 22 Risk Attitude & Axioms of EUT

Sairam

  • Attitudes Towards Risk1

  • Risk Aversion

    • Prospect: \((x_{1},0.5;x_{2},0.5)\)
    • \(E(x) = 0.5x_{1} +0.5x_{2}\) is exactly equidistant from \(x_{1}\) and \(x_{2}\) on the horizontal axis.
    • Vertical axis: \(u(E(x)) = u(0.5x_{1}+0.5x_{2}) \gt E(u(x))\) \(= 0.5u(x_{1}) +0.5u(x_{2})\)
    • So, \(u(E(x)) \gt E(u(x))\)
      • \(E(u(x))\) is halfway through \(u(x_{1})\) and \(u(x_{2})\)
      • \(E(x)\) is halfway through \(x_{1}\) and \(x_{2}\)
      • "Slope of \(u\) between \(E(x)\) and \(x_{2}\)" \(\lt\) "Slope between \(x_{1}\) and \(E(x)\)"
    • Due to diminishing marginal utility. Utility increases at a decreasing rate > As one has more wealth, they would become more risk averse. That's why associates a lower amount of utility to \(x_{2}\) than \(x_{1}\)

    • Definition: \(x_{CE}\) is the certainty equivalent since, \(u(x_{CE}) = 0.5u(x_{1}) + 0.5u(x_{2})\). Yields the same level as expected utility of the gamble, \(E(u(x))\)

      • \(x_{CE} < E(X)\) reflecting that the person is willing to give up some amount of money (on average) in in return for certainty. #doubt How does it reduce uncertainty?

The Axioms of EUT

We will look at axioms and their violations as observed by behavioralists.

Preference symbols: - \(\succ :\) preferred to - \(\sim :\) as good a - \(\succcurlyeq:\) at least as good as

  1. Completeness
    • \(\forall A,B\)
    • \(B \succ A\) or \(A \succ B\) or \(A \sim B\)
  2. Transitivity
    • for three prospects \(A,B,C\)
    • \(A \succcurlyeq B\), \(B \succcurlyeq C\) \(\implies\) \(A \succcurlyeq C\)
    • Order or Ordering Axiom
    • Intransitive Preference: Preference Reversal
      • \(E = A \succ F=C \succ D=B \succ A\)
      • \(\implies A \succ C \succ B \succ A\)
  3. Continuity
    • If \(A \succ B \succ C\) then \(\exists\) probability \(r\) \(\ni\)
      • \(rA + (1-r)C \sim B\)
      • The prospects \((B)\) and \((A,r;\ C, 1-r)\) are indifferent
      • The latter is a Compound Prospect
    • For any \(p > r\)
      • \(pA + (1-p)C \succ B\)
      • and vice-versa (\(p < r\))
  4. Independence ^3a00a1
    • Definition: \(\forall A,B,C\) if \(A \succ B\) then,
      • \((A,p; C,1-p) \succ (B,p; C, 1-p)\) \(\forall p\)
      • i.e. \(C\) doesn't affect the compound prospect's preference order
    • e.g. \(\text{Coffee} \succ \text{Tea}\) and \(P(\text{Rain} )=0.6\)
      • Regardless of rain or not, my preference for coffee over tea will not change
    • e.g. K&T If the probabilities are reduced in equal proportion:
      • \(A = (3000) \succ B = (4000,0.8)\) then,
      • \(A'=(3000,0.25)\) should be \(\succ B'=(4000,0.2)\)
      • Here, \(C = 0\) and \(p = 0.25\)
    • However, K&T found that about 80% of those asked, chose \(A \succ B\), and about 65% would choose \(B' \succ A'\). - #violation!
    • Isolation Effect: Another #violation
      • \((0,0.75; \text{Stage 2}, 0.25)\)
      • Stage 2: \((4000,0.8)\) vs \((3000)\)
        graph LR
            A((Chance: End?)) -->|1/4| B["Choice"]
            A -->|3/4| Z["0"]
            B --> C(("Chance"))
            C -->|4/5| E[4000]
            C -->|1/5| F[0]
            B --> D[3000]
      • In terms of final outcome: the choice is between
        • \((4000, 0.2)\) and \((3000,0.25)\)
        • 78% chose the latter prospect: \((3000,0.25)\)
        • Contradicts: Just the previous K&T (65% people preferred)
      • Evidently, the reason is:
        • People ignored the first stage of the game
        • Considered it a choice between \((3000)\) vs \((4000,0.8)\)
        • "Anyway, the first chance is not in my hands... If I get through, I should not miss the chance." "But wait, if you actually get through the first stage, don't you think you are testing your luck too much by choosing an uncertain option? I mean you are talking about a situation which even more improbable"
      • \(\implies\) Choices are primarily determined by the probabilities of the final state (in isolation)
    • Common Outcome Effect:
      • \(A \succ B\) and \(C \succ D\)
      • If the third column is removed in both then the gambles \(A,C\) are identical and \(B,D\) are identical (with the probabilities)
      • But it was observed, \(A \succ B\) and \(D \succ C\). VIOLATION! Actually not independent!
  5. Monotonicity ^be6d07
    • Let \(x_{1},x_{2}\dots x_{n}\) be outcomes ordered from worse \((x_{1})\) to best \((x_{n})\)
    • Prospect \(q\) stochastically dominates \(r\) ^6eeac7
    • If at least one \(p_{qj} > p_{rj}\) #doubt ==I don't understand what it means. Can the situation be explained please?==
      • People preferred \(B \succ A\)
    • VIOLATION:
      • Out of 124 people, K&T found 60% to prefer: \(C \succ D\)
      • Though \(A \sim C\) and \(B \sim D\) and thus people should have: \(D \sim C\)
    • Reason: People focus on the options more than the probabilities. They look at the gamble with the least number of losses and thus select \(C\).
      • Due to lack of transparency in presentation of the gamble.

  1. Convex or concave to the horizontal axis